World Library  
Flag as Inappropriate
Email this Article

Accident (philosophy)

Article Id: WHEBN0000741128
Reproduction Date:

Title: Accident (philosophy)  
Author: World Heritage Encyclopedia
Language: English
Subject: Substance theory, Modal logic, Aristotelian physics, Ousia, Transubstantiation
Collection: Christian Terminology, Metaphysics, Modal Logic, Philosophical Terminology
Publisher: World Heritage Encyclopedia
Publication
Date:
 

Accident (philosophy)

Accident, as used in philosophy, is an attribute which may or may not belong to a subject, without affecting its essence.[1] The word "accident" has been employed throughout the history of philosophy with several distinct meanings.

Contents

  • Aristotelian substance theory 1
  • Modern philosophy 2
  • See also 3
  • References 4

Aristotelian substance theory

Aristotle made a distinction between the essential and accidental properties of a thing. For example, a chair can be made of wood or metal but this is accidental to its being a chair: that is, it is still a chair regardless of the material from which it is made.[2] To put this in technical terms, an accident is a property which has no necessary connection to the essence of the thing being described.[3][4][5]

To take another example, all bachelors are unmarried: this is a necessary or essential property of what it means to be a bachelor. A particular bachelor may have brown hair, but this would be a property particular to that individual, and with respect to his bachelorhood it would be an accidental property. And this distinction is independent of experimental verification: even if for some reason all the unmarried men with non-brown hair were killed, and every single existent bachelor had brown hair, the property of having brown hair would still be accidental, since it would still be logically possible for a bachelor to have hair of another color.

The nine kinds of accidents according to Aristotle are quantity, quality, relation, habitus, time, location, situation (or position), action, and passion ("being acted on"). Together with "substance", these nine kinds of accidents constitute the ten fundamental categories of Aristotle's ontology.[6]

Catholic theologians such as Thomas Aquinas have employed the Aristotelian concepts of substance and accident in articulating the theology of the Eucharist, particularly the transubstantiation of bread and wine into body and blood. According to this tradition, the accidents of the appearance of bread and wine do not change, but the substance changes from bread and wine to the Body and Blood of Christ.

Modern philosophy

In modern philosophy, an accident (or accidental property) is the union of two concepts: property and contingency. In relation to the first, an accidental property (Greek symbebekos)[7] is at its most basic level a property. The color "yellow", "high value", "Atomic Number 79" are all properties, and are therefore candidates for being accidental. On the other hand, "gold", "platinum", and "electrum" are not properties, and are therefore not classified as accidents.

There are two opposed philosophical positions that also impact the meaning of this term:

  • Anti-Essentialism (associated with Willard Van Orman Quine) argues that there are no essential properties at all, and therefore every property is an accident.
  • Modal Necessitarianism (associated with Saul Kripke), argues for the veracity of the modal system "Triv" (If P is true, then P must be true). The consequence of this theory is that all properties are essential (and no property is an accident).

See also

References

  1. ^ Guthrie, William Keith Chambers (1990). A History of Greek Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 148.  
  2. ^ Thomas (2003). Commentary on Aristotle's Physics. Richard J. Blackwell, Richard J. Spath, W. Edmund Thirlkel. Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 29.  
  3. ^ "Aristotle - Metaphysics: Books Zeta and Eta". SparkNotes. Archived from the original on 18 December 2008. Retrieved 2008-12-19. 
  4. ^ "Aristotle on Non-contradiction". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2007-02-02. Retrieved 2008-12-19. 
  5. ^ Preus, Anthony; John P. Anton; George L. Kustas (1992). Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy V. SUNY Press.  
  6. ^ "Predication and Ontology: The Categories". University of Washington. Retrieved 2008-12-19. 
  7. ^ Slomkowski, Paul (1997). Aristotle's Topics. BRILL. pp. 90–93.  
This article was sourced from Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. World Heritage Encyclopedia content is assembled from numerous content providers, Open Access Publishing, and in compliance with The Fair Access to Science and Technology Research Act (FASTR), Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., Public Library of Science, The Encyclopedia of Life, Open Book Publishers (OBP), PubMed, U.S. National Library of Medicine, National Center for Biotechnology Information, U.S. National Library of Medicine, National Institutes of Health (NIH), U.S. Department of Health & Human Services, and USA.gov, which sources content from all federal, state, local, tribal, and territorial government publication portals (.gov, .mil, .edu). Funding for USA.gov and content contributors is made possible from the U.S. Congress, E-Government Act of 2002.
 
Crowd sourced content that is contributed to World Heritage Encyclopedia is peer reviewed and edited by our editorial staff to ensure quality scholarly research articles.
 
By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. World Heritage Encyclopedia™ is a registered trademark of the World Public Library Association, a non-profit organization.
 


Copyright © World Library Foundation. All rights reserved. eBooks from Project Gutenberg are sponsored by the World Library Foundation,
a 501c(4) Member's Support Non-Profit Organization, and is NOT affiliated with any governmental agency or department.